|
If History Interests You, then This Section of the
Site is For You |
|
Back |
Federalist
No. 76
The Appointing Power of the
Executive
From the New York Packet. Tuesday, April 1, 1788. |
Next |
|
Author: Alexander Hamilton
To the People of the State of New York:
THE President is ``to NOMINATE, and, by and with the advice and
consent of the Senate, to appoint ambassadors, other public
ministers and consuls, judges of the Supreme Court, and all
other officers of the United States whose appointments are not
otherwise provided for in the Constitution. But the Congress may
by law vest the appointment of such inferior officers as they
think proper, in the President alone, or in the courts of law,
or in the heads of departments. The President shall have power
to fill up ALL VACANCIES which may happen DURING THE RECESS OF
THE SENATE, by granting commissions which shall EXPIRE at the
end of their next session.''
It has been observed in a former paper, that ``the true test of
a good government is its aptitude and tendency to produce a good
administration.'' If the justness of this observation be
admitted, the mode of appointing the officers of the United
States contained in the foregoing clauses, must, when examined,
be allowed to be entitled to particular commendation. It is not
easy to conceive a plan better calculated than this to promote a
judicious choice of men for filling the offices of the Union;
and it will not need proof, that on this point must essentially
depend the character of its administration.
It will be agreed on all hands, that the power of appointment,
in ordinary cases, ought to be modified in one of three ways. It
ought either to be vested in a single man, or in a SELECT
assembly of a moderate number; or in a single man, with the
concurrence of such an assembly. The exercise of it by the
people at large will be readily admitted to be impracticable; as
waiving every other consideration, it would leave them little
time to do anything else. When, therefore, mention is made in
the subsequent reasonings of an assembly or body of men, what is
said must be understood to relate to a select body or assembly,
of the description already given. The people collectively, from
their number and from their dispersed situation, cannot be
regulated in their movements by that systematic spirit of cabal
and intrigue, which will be urged as the chief objections to
reposing the power in question in a body of men.
Those who have themselves reflected upon the subject, or who
have attended to the observations made in other parts of these
papers, in relation to the appointment of the President, will, I
presume, agree to the position, that there would always be great
probability of having the place supplied by a man of abilities,
at least respectable. Premising this, I proceed to lay it down
as a rule, that one man of discernment is better fitted to
analyze and estimate the peculiar qualities adapted to
particular offices, than a body of men of equal or perhaps even
of superior discernment.
The sole and undivided responsibility of one man will naturally
beget a livelier sense of duty and a more exact regard to
reputation. He will, on this account, feel himself under
stronger obligations, and more interested to investigate with
care the qualities requisite to the stations to be filled, and
to prefer with impartiality the persons who may have the fairest
pretensions to them. He will have FEWER personal attachments to
gratify, than a body of men who may each be supposed to have an
equal number; and will be so much the less liable to be misled
by the sentiments of friendship and of affection. A single
well-directed man, by a single understanding, cannot be
distracted and warped by that diversity of views, feelings, and
interests, which frequently distract and warp the resolutions of
a collective body. There is nothing so apt to agitate the
passions of mankind as personal considerations whether they
relate to ourselves or to others, who are to be the objects of
our choice or preference. Hence, in every exercise of the power
of appointing to offices, by an assembly of men, we must expect
to see a full display of all the private and party likings and
dislikes, partialities and antipathies, attachments and
animosities, which are felt by those who compose the assembly.
The choice which may at any time happen to be made under such
circumstances, will of course be the result either of a victory
gained by one party over the other, or of a compromise between
the parties. In either case, the intrinsic merit of the
candidate will be too often out of sight. In the first, the
qualifications best adapted to uniting the suffrages of the
party, will be more considered than those which fit the person
for the station. In the last, the coalition will commonly turn
upon some interested equivalent: ``Give us the man we wish for
this office, and you shall have the one you wish for that.''
This will be the usual condition of the bargain. And it will
rarely happen that the advancement of the public service will be
the primary object either of party victories or of party
negotiations.
The truth of the principles here advanced seems to have been
felt by the most intelligent of those who have found fault with
the provision made, in this respect, by the convention. They
contend that the President ought solely to have been authorized
to make the appointments under the federal government. But it is
easy to show, that every advantage to be expected from such an
arrangement would, in substance, be derived from the power of
NOMINATION, which is proposed to be conferred upon him; while
several disadvantages which might attend the absolute power of
appointment in the hands of that officer would be avoided. In
the act of nomination, his judgment alone would be exercised;
and as it would be his sole duty to point out the man who, with
the approbation of the Senate, should fill an office, his
responsibility would be as complete as if he were to make the
final appointment. There can, in this view, be no difference
others, who are to be the objects of our choice or preference.
Hence, in every exercise of the power of appointing to offices,
by an assembly of men, we must expect to see a full display of
all the private and party likings and dislikes, partialities and
antipathies, attachments and animosities, which are felt by
those who compose the assembly. The choice which may at any time
happen to be made under such circumstances, will of course be
the result either of a victory gained by one party over the
other, or of a compromise between the parties. In either case,
the intrinsic merit of the candidate will be too often out of
sight. In the first, the qualifications best adapted to uniting
the suffrages of the party, will be more considered than those
which fit the person for the station. In the last, the coalition
will commonly turn upon some interested equivalent: ``Give us
the man we wish for this office, and you shall have the one you
wish for that.'' This will be the usual condition of the
bargain. And it will rarely happen that the advancement of the
public service will be the primary object either of party
victories or of party negotiations.
The truth of the principles here advanced seems to have been
felt by the most intelligent of those who have found fault with
the provision made, in this respect, by the convention. They
contend that the President ought solely to have been authorized
to make the appointments under the federal government. But it is
easy to show, that every advantage to be expected from such an
arrangement would, in substance, be derived from the power of
NOMINATION, which is proposed to be conferred upon him; while
several disadvantages which might attend the absolute power of
appointment in the hands of that officer would be avoided. In
the act of nomination, his judgment alone would be exercised;
and as it would be his sole duty to point out the man who, with
the approbation of the Senate, should fill an office, his
responsibility would be as complete as if he were to make the
final appointment. There can, in this view, be no difference
between nominating and appointing. The same motives which would
influence a proper discharge of his duty in one case, would
exist in the other. And as no man could be appointed but on his
previous nomination, every man who might be appointed would be,
in fact, his choice.
But might not his nomination be overruled? I grant it might, yet
this could only be to make place for another nomination by
himself. The person ultimately appointed must be the object of
his preference, though perhaps not in the first degree. It is
also not very probable that his nomination would often be
overruled. The Senate could not be tempted, by the preference
they might feel to another, to reject the one proposed; because
they could not assure themselves, that the person they might
wish would be brought forward by a second or by any subsequent
nomination. They could not even be certain, that a future
nomination would present a candidate in any degree more
acceptable to them; and as their dissent might cast a kind of
stigma upon the individual rejected, and might have the
appearance of a reflection upon the judgment of the chief
magistrate, it is not likely that their sanction would often be
refused, where there were not special and strong reasons for the
refusal.
To what purpose then require the co-operation of the Senate? I
answer, that the necessity of their concurrence would have a
powerful, though, in general, a silent operation. It would be an
excellent check upon a spirit of favoritism in the President,
and would tend greatly to prevent the appointment of unfit
characters from State prejudice, from family connection, from
personal attachment, or from a view to popularity. In addition
to this, it would be an efficacious source of stability in the
administration.
It will readily be comprehended, that a man who had himself the
sole disposition of offices, would be governed much more by his
private inclinations and interests, than when he was bound to
submit the propriety of his choice to the discussion and
determination of a different and independent body, and that body
an entire branch of the legislature. The possibility of
rejection would be a strong motive to care in proposing. The
danger to his own reputation, and, in the case of an elective
magistrate, to his political existence, from betraying a spirit
of favoritism, or an unbecoming pursuit of popularity, to the
observation of a body whose opinion would have great weight in
forming that of the public, could not fail to operate as a
barrier to the one and to the other. He would be both ashamed
and afraid to bring forward, for the most distinguished or
lucrative stations, candidates who had no other merit than that
of coming from the same State to which he particularly belonged,
or of being in some way or other personally allied to him, or of
possessing the necessary insignificance and pliancy to render
them the obsequious instruments of his pleasure.
To this reasoning it has been objected that the President, by
the influence of the power of nomination, may secure the
complaisance of the Senate to his views. This supposition of
universal venality in human nature is little less an error in
political reasoning, than the supposition of universal
rectitude. The institution of delegated power implies, that
there is a portion of virtue and honor among mankind, which may
be a reasonable foundation of confidence; and experience
justifies the theory. It has been found to exist in the most
corrupt periods of the most corrupt governments. The venality of
the British House of Commons has been long a topic of accusation
against that body, in the country to which they belong as well
as in this; and it cannot be doubted that the charge is, to a
considerable extent, well founded. But it is as little to be
doubted, that there is always a large proportion of the body,
which consists of independent and public-spirited men, who have
an influential weight in the councils of the nation. Hence it is
(the present reign not excepted) that the sense of that body is
often seen to control the inclinations of the monarch, both with
regard to men and to measures. Though it might therefore be
allowable to suppose that the Executive might occasionally
influence some individuals in the Senate, yet the supposition,
that he could in general purchase the integrity of the whole
body, would be forced and improbable. A man disposed to view
human nature as it is, without either flattering its virtues or
exaggerating its vices, will see sufficient ground of confidence
in the probity of the Senate, to rest satisfied, not only that
it will be impracticable to the Executive to corrupt or seduce a
majority of its members, but that the necessity of its
co-operation, in the business of appointments, will be a
considerable and salutary restraint upon the conduct of that
magistrate. Nor is the integrity of the Senate the only
reliance. The Constitution has provided some important guards
against the danger of executive influence upon the legislative
body: it declares that ``No senator or representative shall
during the time FOR WHICH HE WAS ELECTED, be appointed to any
civil office under the United States, which shall have been
created, or the emoluments whereof shall have been increased,
during such time; and no person, holding any office under the
United States, shall be a member of either house during his
continuance in office.''
PUBLIUS. |
|
|
|
|